Notes on Human Nature

It seems to me that many of our political views, especially the ones we find ourselves least willing to fudge, depend crucially on what we take human nature to be.  But we can ask a prior question, and I think asking it might be a better place to start.  

Is there a singular human nature, or or are people truly diverse?  Is each mind a new construction — an alien, finally, to her peers?  Or do we all have something very deep in common?  And is that deep commonality, should there be one, enough to justify a social order which cherishes its nourishment, or a revolution to install a social order which does?

To begin at the beginning . . .

Aristotle argued that in order to grasp true human happiness, one must first understand the function of a human being.  Aristotle did not mean: the function of this or that human being.  He meant the function of, as it were, all of them — the function of being human.  Happiness would be the fulfilment of that function, whatever it turned out to be.

Just as this or that profession, or this or that kind of tool, has each its purpose, to be performed well or badly, so too, thought Aristotle, did each species.  Human beings were no exception.  Happiness for humans, then, would be fulfilment of the human function.

Aristotle wrote, in the Nichomachean Ethics, Book 1, Chapter 7:

Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good seems a platitude, and a clearer account of what it is still desired. This might perhaps be given, if we could first ascertain the function of man. For just as for a flute-player, a sculptor, or an artist, and, in general, for all things that have a function or activity, the good and the ‘well’ is thought to reside in the function, so would it seem to be for man, if he has a function. Have the carpenter, then, and the tanner certain functions or activities, and has man none?  Is he born without a function? Or as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts evidently has a function, may one lay it down that man similarly has a function apart from all these? What then can this be?

What is the human function?  What is, to put it differently, our purpose?

Aristotle’s answer was:

[W]e state the function of man to be a certain kind of life, and this to be an activity or actions of the soul implying a rational principle, and the function of a good man to be the good and noble performance of these, and if any action is well performed when it is performed in accordance with the appropriate excellence: if this is the case, human good turns out to be activity of soul in accordance with virtue, and if there are more than one virtue, in accordance with the best and most complete.

The “best and most complete virtue” turned out, for Aristotle, to be “justice”.  This is why the Nichomachean Ethics is followed, with nary a pause for breath, by the Politics.  The function of the human is activity of the soul in accordance with “justice”.

But what interests me here, now, is not Aristotle’s conclusion but his method of argument.  He claims that to find human happiness, one must first establish the unique function of humanity.  On this line of thinking, if there is no species-determinate function, no human nature, then there is nothing to fulfill, and so no true happiness to be had.  

This is a bold claim.  It is a claim that there is a singular human nature which can be either fulfilled or not fulfilled by this Jane or that Tom.  

Leaping forward two-thousand, three hundred years, we find a contemporary of ours making a strikingly similar argument.

QUESTION [Kate Soper]: You have argued that any stance one takes on political, economic, social or even personal issues is ultimately based on some conception of human nature. Why is this?

[Noam] CHOMSKY: Any stance we take is based on some conception of what is good for people. This conception will tacitly presuppose a certain belief as to the constitution of human nature — human needs and human potential. You might as well bring them out as clearly as possible so that they can be discussed.

QUESTION: According to your view of human nature, all human beings possess certain biological functions endowing them with common mental capacities. How do you defend this position against postmodernist critics who argue that there is no such thing as human nature, and that all attempts to define it are guilty of reading other cultures in the light of Western perceptions and values?

CHOMSKY: Not even the most extreme postmodernist can seriously argue that there is no such thing as human nature. They may argue that the exact properties of human nature are difficult to substantiate — this is certainly correct. However, it is impossible to coherently argue that an intrinsic, universal human nature does not exist. This amounts to the belief that the next human zygote conceived might just as well develop into a worm or a crab as a human being. Postmodernists might limit their assertion to denying any effect of human nature on our mental make-up — our values, our knowledge, our wants, etc. This also makes no sense. The postmodernist will argue that a child growing up in New York will develop a certain way of thinking, and if that child had grown up amongst Amazon tribespeople she would have developed a completely different way of thinking. This is true. But we must then ask how a child could develop these different consciousnesses. In whatever environment it finds itself, the child will mentally construct a rich and complex culture on the basis of the extremely scattered and limited phenomena it is exposed to. That consideration tells us (in advance of any detailed knowledge) that there must be an extraordinary directive and organisational component to the mind that is internal. We can begin to see human nature in terms of certain capacities to develop certain mental traits. I think we can go further than this and begin to discover universal aspects of these mental traits which are determined by human nature. I think we can find this in the area of morality. For example, not long ago I talked to people in Amazon tribes and I took it for granted that they have the same conception of vice and virtue as I do. It is only through sharing these values that we were able to interact — talking about real problems such as being forced out of the jungle by the state authorities. I believe I was correct to assume this: we had no problem communicating although we were as remote as is possible culturally.

QUESTION: Are you suggesting everyone agrees about the nature of vice and virtue?

CHOMSKY: In fact I think they probably have a very high measure of agreement. One strong bit of evidence for this is that everyone — a Genghis Khan, Himmler, Bill Gates — creates stories of themselves where they interpret their actions as working for the benefit of human beings. Even at the extreme levels of depravity, the Nazis did not boast that they wanted to kill Jews, but gave crazed justifications — even that they were acting in ‘self-defence’. It is very rare for people to justify their actions by saying ‘I’m doing this to maximise my own benefit and I don’t care what happens to anybody else’. That would be pathological.

That’s a pretty complicated exchange, to be sure.  I want, right now, just to point out that “the most extreme postmodernist” can indeed argue seriously that there is no such thing as human nature.  Not only can they, they have.

In a fairly famous debate with Chomsky, Michel Foucault (whether he would have liked the characterization “post-modern” I am not sure) argued as follows:

Where perhaps I don’t completely agree with Mr. Chomsky, is when he places the principle of these regularities, in a way, in the interior of the mind or of human nature.

  If it is a matter of whether these rules are effectively put to work by the human mind, all right; all right, too, if it is a question of whether the historian and the linguist can think it in their turn; it is all right also to say that these rules should allow us to realise what is said or thought by these individuals. But to say that these regularities are connected, as conditions of existence, to the human mind or its nature, is difficult for me to accept: it seems to me that one must, before reaching that point-and in any case I am talking only about the understanding-replace it in the field of other human practices, such as economics, technology, politics, sociology, which can serve them as conditions of formation, of models, of place, of apparition, etc. I would like to know whether one cannot discover the system of regularity, of constraint, which makes science possible, somewhere else, even outside the human mind, in social forms, in the relations of production, in the class struggles, etc.

Foucault thought that claims of human nature were likely as not impositions on freedom, from the outside.

Richard Rorty argues the point more directly when he argues that claims to have found the true human nature are necessarily impositions on freedom — freedom to create one’s own nature.

It is with this kind of background that Rorty begins to develop his argument that the best way to foster a human rights respecting society is through the use of educational sentimentality.  Rorty begins his argument in his paper Human Rights, Rationality and Sentimentality by making the bold claim that rather than asking the question “what is our nature?” we ought to ask the question “what can we make of ourselves?”  We should not take theories of human nature seriously, but rather come to see ourselves as malleable, flexible and self-shaping animals capable of morphing with the culture.  We are not to be viewed as rational or cruel animals, but rather as changing animals (169-170 [of Contingency, Irony and Solidarity]).  As discussed above, Rorty finds theories of the nature of humanity to miss the point entirely.  They presuppose that one could get outside of one’s own web of belief to discover exactly what it was based on.  

We can get a little into the weeds, here.  A libertarian might argue that there is no predetermined human nature, and so the only appropriate social order would be the one which most maximizes the freedom to construct natures, to find goods, to create meaning.

On the other hand, a libertarian could go so far as to agree with Karl Marx, who wrote that there is one human nature, and that it is to engage in creative work.  In the Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, Marx wrote:

The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It is not distinct from that activity; it is that activity. Man makes his life activity itself an object of his will and consciousness. He has conscious life activity. It is not a determination with which he directly merges. Conscious life activity directly distinguishes man from animal life activity. Only because of that is he a species-being. Or, rather, he is a conscious being – i.e., his own life is an object for him, only because he is a species-being. Only because of that is his activity free activity. Estranged labour reverses the relationship so that man, just because he is a conscious being, makes his life activity, his essential being, a mere means for his existence.

In this way, a vision of human nature could be claimed to underwrite “true Communism” and, one assumes, its polar opposite, libertarianism.  Ayn Rand’s libertarianism was underwritten by a conception of human nature inspired, in part, by Aristotle, and Aristotle’s conception is not so radically different from Marx’s.

Whether the socialist, or the libertarian, or the liberal, or the fascist, can or ought to hang their claims from a conception of human nature is certainly open to debate.  But I am willing to bet that many, in fact, do, at least implicitly.  This is an invitiation to reflect on the matter.

35 comments

Skip to comment form

  1. Please share some other writers with us, on the subject of human nature.  Share your own, too!

  2. … to me, a human being’s function is fulfilled the moment she or he is born — to exist.  Existence.  Period.

    I’m of the “interconnectedness” school of thought.  I think we are literally interedependent and are all physically part of the same thing, both existentially (existence) and spatially (the universe).

    Given that, to find and apprehend one’s place in the universe (literally again, both existentially and spacially) would be to find one’s “human” nature.

  3. and cross-foster each in the other’s life.

  4. Chomsky have always proven to be beneficial efforts.

    I’d have to agree with Nightprowl on the existence period point.  If you kill anything you are ending it’s existence.

    Happiness has many levels, am I happy to sit down and watch the football game?  Yup, am I happy building something?  Yup.  Is it more beneficial to the society if I partake in a social event or if I build something for the community?  

    This is where all of the gray areas of philosophy reveal themselves and I tend to step back…one man’s words many years ago did not necessarily have the same meaning.  Even back then the concept of happiness was a multileveled instrument that could be tipped in anyone’s favor just like statistics can be tilted in anyone’s favor.

    This is a great discussion however as I ended up sleeping through many of my first level philosophy courses and hope their are better minds out there that will help us all to understand philosophy a little better.

    It’s probably due to The Church but I’m a parable guy, I like stories that teach without preaching and wisdom gained from real experiences of others over a search for the perfect words to describe the human experience.

  5. in as much as there are as many different stories to be worked out (natures to be discovered) as there are individuals.  The archetypes we find throughout humankind’s existence (though certainly products of our own views), particularly the archetype of ‘wholeness’ and the individuation process through understanding and integration of the ‘shadow’, point me in the direction of a ‘nature’ that is to continually discover what it doesn’t know about itself.

  6. Now, why do the various animals do what seem to us such strange things , in the presence of such outlandish stimuli? Why does the hen, for example, submit herself to the tedium of incubating such a fearfully uninteresting set of objects as a nestful of eggs, unless she have some sort of a prophetic inkling of the result? The only answer is ad hominem. We can only interpret the instincts of brutes by what we know of instincts in ourselves. Why do men always lie down, when they can, on soft beds rather than on hard floors? Why do they sit round the stove on a cold day? ‘Why, in a, room, do they place themselves, ninety-nine times out of a hundred, with their faces towards its middle rather than to the wall ? Why do they prefer saddle of mutton and champagne to hard-tack and ditch-water? Why does the maiden interest the youth so that everything about her seems more important and significant than anything else in the world? Nothing more can be said than that these are human ways, and that every creature likes its own ways, and takes to the following them as a, matter of course. Science may come and consider these ways, and find that most of them are useful. But it is not for the sake of their utility that they are followed, but because at the moment of following them we feel that that is the only appropriate and natural thing to do. Not one man in a billion, when taking his dinner, ever thinks of utility. He eats because the food tastes good and makes him want more. If you ask him why he should want to eat more of what tastes like that, instead of revering you as a philosopher he will probably laugh at you for a fool. The connection between the savory sensation and the act it awakens is for him absolute and selbstverständlich, an ‘ a priori syn- [p. 387] thesis’ of the most perfect sort, needing no proof but its own evidence. It takes, in short, what Berkeley calls a mind debauched by learning to carry the process of making the natural seem strange, so far as to ask for the why of any instinctive human act. To the metaphysician alone can such questions occur as: Why do we smile, when pleased, and not scowl? Why are we unable to talk to a crowd as we talk to a single friend? Why does a particular maiden turn our wits so upside-down? The common man can only say, ” Of course we smile, of course our heart palpitates at the sight of the crowd, of course we love the maiden, that beautiful soul clad in that perfect form, so palpably and flagrantly made from all eternity to be loved !”

    Unlike many modern thinkers, James felt that humans had a proliferation of instincts.

  7. Would they have to reconsider their entire base having lived in the age of instant “communications”.

    Yes, some of you already know the link.

    http://www.scl.cc/home.php

  8. They live, for instance, in all sorts of climates.  Their distant ape cousins only live in the tropics, or in zoos.  They eat all kinds of stuff, even meat 😛  They have all sorts of belief systems, and do all sorts of things based on them.  Sure, they’ve all got pleasure and pain receptors in the same places, the same tolerances for heat and cold and hunger and the like, and a lot of the same cultural motifs.  But then they surprise you — committing suicide en masse, or developing new cultures out of whole cloth, or coming up with stuff like nanotechnology.

    But before we nail down “human nature” as being this and not that, let’s try to expand the versatility thing.  We’ll have to count on it, for instance, to deal with abrupt climate change.

    And evolutionary psychology is a bunch of neo-liberal genetics, for all that it tries to nail down “human nature” too soon.  

  9. humans easily have basic instincts observable in many mammals.  However, they are more differentiated.

    Rather than make a long list, let me provide a single example of a differentiation of an instinctive impulse in humans: Laughter.  Everyone laughs.  Chimps laugh too.  If you tickle a chimp, his laughter (breathing) goes in and out: ungh-whoo, ungh-whoo.  When you tickle a human you elicit staccato outbursts only (ha-ha-ha), from which one sometimes needs to recover to literally catch a breath.  If you put a microphone in front of someone on the street and ask them if they laugh, the most common response is laughter.  People laugh most at their own jokes.  

    Chimps don’t laugh at all the same things we do, and they don’t laugh in the same way, but both chimps and humans laugh.

  10. Like nightprowlkitty I am of the interconnected school of thinking – I think the entire universe is interconnected on a basis as small as an atom – or smaller. Further, I believe that the current disfunction we are seeing in humanity is a direct reflection of what is happening to the very air we breathe, the earth we step on. In others words each and every being is connected with the physical elements surrounding us. For me the baaic question is: from what we are observing, are we heading towards extinction? I hope not. But it appears we may well be

    • xenic on December 3, 2007 at 04:46

    Lithium

    Manic Depressive

    Paranoic

    Obsessive Depressive

    Attention Deficit Disorder

    Sociopath

    Psychotic

    Autistic

    Artistic

    Genius

    Obviously, there is great variation in the human mind, and this variation spills in many dimensions.  Did I mention homosexuality?, fetishism?   – what of the rest of the body, and the body and experience taken as a whole?  Each individual is truely and radically unique, and we all have that in common.

  11. Humans are animals…so there is an animal nature that informs and often overrides the true human nature. Separating the two is tricky, since you have to determine if the human nature in question is just a more highly developed extension of animal nature

    Survival is animal nature….expanding on that nature to accumulate more money to help you survive is human nature, but is that just an extension to animal nature granted through the human capacity to reason and see consequences?

    Greed drives folks to accumulate more than they will ever need for survival, but it is based on survival.

    Seeking fairness (justice) is human nature, learning, (past an instinctual point) striving for better is human nature, imo. But I could be wrong! Improving the lives of others……generosity, perhaps….or is that just a clever animal instinctively practicing game theory?

    Protecting your young, your pack, extends to protecting your tribe. How far does that penetrate the formation of societies or governments?

    Then their is cruelty and a general destructive capacity that seems uniquely human too.

    On the practical level…I want humans to pursue happiness, happy humans tend to do less damage.

    On the ideal level….I want people to proceed from a position of For The Greatest Good Of All Concerned.

    Ok, I will say that to learn, to strive and to make life better is one side of human nature, the other side of human nature is cruelty and pointless destruction. Learning to, striving to, and succeeding in making better the part of human nature that is cruel and destructive would be fulfillment.

  12. not much!

    Diversity occurs only in which part of the spectrum of human nature one focuses on.

    • pico on December 3, 2007 at 07:06

    I think you’re skipping a few steps here:

    On [Aristotle’s] line of thinking, if there is no species-determinate function, no human nature, then there is nothing to fulfill, and so no true happiness to be had.

    Strictly speaking, if we follow Aristotle’s line of thinking, we come to slightly different conclusions: if there is no species-determinate function, then there is nothing to fulfill at the level of species, and so no true happiness to be had at the level of species.  Just as the failure to find a fulfilling function for the human being doesn’t preclude the existence of a fulfilling function for the hand or the foot, the failure of a species-wide function doesn’t preclude true happiness if we find a determinate function in the individual or smaller group.

    Now, I’ll agree that Aristotle would never buy this line, because he believes that there IS a species determinate function.  But the failure to find one only cancels out his conclusions according to his original terms, not necessarily others (individual- or group-determinate functions).

    I’m impressed by how well you bring all these seemingly disparate philosophies together, by the way.  Marx and Rand, holding hands on the seashore.  

    As for human nature, I have no idea.  It’s another of those “we can’t see it ’cause we’re inside it” questions, which may be a cop out, but there ya go.  It may be that we’re laughable simple (and predictable) from an outside point of view, but an outsider who understood it might not be able to communicate it in terms we could understand.  But I can safely say that people who make claims about human nature seem to me to oversimplify, or to make sweeping judgments just begging for exceptions.

    Does that mean, Ă  la Aristotle, that we don’t have a function or path to happiness?  Maybe not as a group, but individuals seem to do okay.  Often at the expense of others.  Does that mean they aren’t truly happy?  Only if we consider happiness of the species a greater value, right?   So do we end up back at Aristotle?

    – a little rambling, but I’m tired, sorry.

Comments have been disabled.